Being a little let's call it resourceful: this week's post is an excerpt from my paper. If you're interested in the psychology of early genital surgery or how male circumcision might weigh in on this argument, here you are:
Often,
the first response to a baby being born is two questions: 1) is it healthy? and
2) is it a boy or a girl? For perhaps 1.7% of newborns, the answer to the
latter is not obvious and causes significant distress for the parents. Before a
now-controversial publication by John Money in 1955, society was unsure of what
to do in these situations – if anything even needed to be done. His essay,
“Hermaphroditism: Recommendations concerning assignment of sex, change of sex,
and psychological management” established the standard practices by which many
physicians still operate today, claiming that early sex assignment – often achieved
by genital correction surgery – is the key to maximizing the likelihood of a successful
gender identity formation. Just recently, however, as the children directly affected
by Money’s encouragement to perform genital surgery have become adults, are we
beginning to question this suggested practice.
In
her essay “Should There Only Be Two Sexes?” Anne Fausto-Sterling, a professor
of Biology and Gender Studies at Brown University, questions the practice of
genital surgery asserted by Money: “However well-intentioned, the methods for
managing intersexuality, so entrenched since the 1950’s, have done serious
harm” (Fausto-Sterling, 2000, p. 125). Indeed, she argues for a redefinition of
our binary sexed world and offers new guidelines on how doctors should handle
intersexuality. Following careful consideration of the competing claims of
Money and Fausto-Sterling and the examination of psychological evidence
provided by Slijper’s et al. (1998) study, I argue that early genital surgery
should not be performed in cases of neonate genital ambiguity.
Fausto-Sterling’s
claim that “medicine’s focus on creating the proper genitals, meant to prevent
psychological suffering, clearly contributes to it” was not enough to satisfy
me (Fausto-Sterling, 2000, p.128). Without any specific evidence of the
psychological studies to which she refers, I could not fully accept her
argument, so I located a research study that she references by Slijper et al.
in 1998. It describes the investigation of 59 children with a physical intersex
condition over a ten-year period. A team of healthcare professionals, spanning
several disciplines, at Sophia’s Children Hospital in The Netherlands sought to
prevent the development of cross-gender identification in this sample of intersex
children. To this aim, newborns were each assigned a sex and were surgically
modified to fit that sex within the first year of life. Following surgery, the
children and their parents participated in psychotherapy for the duration of
the study in accordance with John Money’s guidelines for treating intersex
patients.
The
researchers investigated the rates of the development of general
psychopathology, gender identity disorder, and gender behavior deviance. Not
surprisingly, the children seemed to cope more successfully when they displayed
a flexible and resilient personality. Despite this and Money’s supposition that
early genital surgery increases life satisfaction, 39% of the children
developed severe general psychopathology including depressive neurosis and
anxiety as determined by diagnostic criteria outlined in the DSM-IV.
Additionally, 13% of the girls exhibited gender identity disorder (GID). While
these results indicate that early counseling and parental support seem to have some
preventive effect, psychopathology and GID still developed at
higher-than-average rates in the children, which should implicate some doubt for
the efficacy of surgical treatment of intersex children.
“We protest the practice of genital mutilation
in other cultures, but tolerate them at home” (Fausto-Sterling, 2000, p. 125).
This bold comment from Fausto-Sterling prompted me to also think about the
practice of male circumcision in light of the present argument. Canadian nurse
and social advocate Kira Antinuk writes about what she calls forced nontherapeutic
genital cutting in light of both intersex genital surgery and male
circumcision, drawing riveting parallels between the two (Antinuk, 2013). She
argues, like Fausto-Sterling does for infant genital surgery, that the practice
of circumcision serves no physical or medical benefit and that performing such
a procedure is in fact genital mutilation. Additionally, Antinuk posits that
children should at the very least be granted the opportunity to choose to be
circumcised, just as intersex children should have the opportunity to choose
their gender upon reaching an appropriate age.
Can
it be argued that early genital surgery in the case of intersex infants is
forced nontherapeutic genital cutting? I think so. Like circumcision, the
pretense of doing what is best for the child or conforming to social norms
clouds our judgment and prevents us from seeing it that way. If these
procedures were deemed medically necessary to save the child’s life or improve
his/her physical well-being, then obviously medical steps should be taken to
reach those ends. But that is not the case we are describing here. Still it
seems that genital mutilation, which Western society finds deplorable, is
occurring here at home more than we would like to know.
Given this, it is imperative that we better understand the
intricate interplay among mainstream Western society’s established gender
norms, medicine’s role in condoning early genital surgery, and parents’ wish
both to accept children as they are and to shape them in accordance with societal
norms. The most conclusive way to do this is to empirically study these
individuals; however, at present there exists no systematic comparison of
long-term psychological outcomes between intersex individuals who did have
early genital surgery and those who did not, making it difficult to reach a verdict
on the efficacy of early genital surgery.
While there is no denying that the practice of genital surgery confirms
the binary sex system we currently live in, questions about whether to enforce
the binary at the expense of newborns by performing unnecessary surgeries on
them may be less clear. The real shame in all this is that genital surgery has
not even proven effective; in addition to the problems Fausto-Sterling raises, some
women who have chosen genital surgery for intersex conditions as adults found
that surgery, which was supposed to fix appearance and sexual function, failed
to solve either of those problems. While this may be true, it is important to realize
that medical professionals do not intend to harm; indeed, they do the opposite.
It is just in this case that the once-accepted practice of infant genital
surgery to correct a social (not medical) problem must be reevaluated. It seems
that whether early genital surgery is performed or not, intersex individuals
will face major identity and psychological crises later in life. Therefore, I am
inclined to say that if intersex individuals incur similar psychological damage
with or without infant genital surgery, then we should avoid the removal or
alteration of organs the individual might later identify with. By allowing the
child to remain biologically ambiguous, you allow her to decide her gender at
an appropriate age without removing the biological organs that she might one
day want.
No comments:
Post a Comment